Dubins–Spanier theoremsThe Dubins–Spanier theorems are several theorems in the theory of fair cake-cutting. They were published by Lester Dubins and Edwin Spanier in 1961.[1] Although the original motivation for these theorems is fair division, they are in fact general theorems in measure theory. SettingThere is a set , and a set which is a sigma-algebra of subsets of . There are partners. Every partner has a personal value measure . This function determines how much each subset of is worth to that partner. Let a partition of to measurable sets: . Define the matrix as the following matrix: This matrix contains the valuations of all players to all pieces of the partition. Let be the collection of all such matrices (for the same value measures, the same , and different partitions): The Dubins–Spanier theorems deal with the topological properties of . StatementsIf all value measures are countably-additive and nonatomic, then:
This was already proved by Dvoretzky, Wald, and Wolfowitz.[2] CorollariesConsensus partitionA cake partition to k pieces is called a consensus partition with weights (also called exact division) if: I.e, there is a consensus among all partners that the value of piece j is exactly . Suppose, from now on, that are weights whose sum is 1: and the value measures are normalized such that each partner values the entire cake as exactly 1: The convexity part of the DS theorem implies that:[1]: 5
PROOF: For every , define a partition as follows: In the partition , all partners value the -th piece as 1 and all other pieces as 0. Hence, in the matrix , there are ones on the -th column and zeros everywhere else. By convexity, there is a partition such that: In that matrix, the -th column contains only the value . This means that, in the partition , all partners value the -th piece as exactly . Note: this corollary confirms a previous assertion by Hugo Steinhaus. It also gives an affirmative answer to the problem of the Nile provided that there are only a finite number of flood heights. Super-proportional divisionA cake partition to n pieces (one piece per partner) is called a super-proportional division with weights if: I.e, the piece allotted to partner is strictly more valuable for him than what he deserves. The following statement is Dubins-Spanier Theorem on the existence of super-proportional division : 6 Theorem—With these notations, let be weights whose sum is 1, assume that the point is an interior point of the (n-1)-dimensional simplex with coordinates pairwise different, and assume that the value measures are normalized such that each partner values the entire cake as exactly 1 (i.e. they are non-atomic probability measures). If at least two of the measures are not equal ( ), then super-proportional divisions exist. The hypothesis that the value measures are not identical is necessary. Otherwise, the sum leads to a contradiction. Namely, if all value measures are countably-additive and non-atomic, and if there are two partners such that , then a super-proportional division exists.I.e, the necessary condition is also sufficient. Sketch of ProofSuppose w.l.o.g. that . Then there is some piece of the cake, , such that . Let be the complement of ; then . This means that . However, . Hence, either or . Suppose w.l.o.g. that and are true. Define the following partitions:
Here, we are interested only in the diagonals of the matrices , which represent the valuations of the partners to their own pieces:
By convexity, for every set of weights there is a partition such that: It is possible to select the weights such that, in the diagonal of , the entries are in the same ratios as the weights . Since we assumed that , it is possible to prove that , so is a super-proportional division. Utilitarian-optimal divisionA cake partition to n pieces (one piece per partner) is called utilitarian-optimal if it maximizes the sum of values. I.e, it maximizes: Utilitarian-optimal divisions do not always exist. For example, suppose is the set of positive integers. There are two partners. Both value the entire set as 1. Partner 1 assigns a positive value to every integer and partner 2 assigns zero value to every finite subset. From a utilitarian point of view, it is best to give partner 1 a large finite subset and give the remainder to partner 2. When the set given to partner 1 becomes larger and larger, the sum-of-values becomes closer and closer to 2, but it never approaches 2. So there is no utilitarian-optimal division. The problem with the above example is that the value measure of partner 2 is finitely-additive but not countably-additive. The compactness part of the DS theorem immediately implies that:[1]: 7
In this special case, non-atomicity is not required: if all value measures are countably-additive, then a utilitarian-optimal partition exists.[1]: 7 Leximin-optimal divisionA cake partition to n pieces (one piece per partner) is called leximin-optimal with weights if it maximizes the lexicographically-ordered vector of relative values. I.e, it maximizes the following vector: where the partners are indexed such that: A leximin-optimal partition maximizes the value of the poorest partner (relative to his weight); subject to that, it maximizes the value of the next-poorest partner (relative to his weight); etc. The compactness part of the DS theorem immediately implies that:[1]: 8
Further developments
See alsoReferences
|
Portal di Ensiklopedia Dunia