Concept in mathematics
In set theory, a mathematical discipline, the Jensen hierarchy or J-hierarchy is a modification of Gödel's constructible hierarchy, L, that circumvents certain technical difficulties that exist in the constructible hierarchy. The J-Hierarchy figures prominently in fine structure theory, a field pioneered by Ronald Jensen, for whom the Jensen hierarchy is named. Rudimentary functions describe a method for iterating through the Jensen hierarchy.
Definition
As in the definition of L, let Def(X) be the collection of sets definable with parameters over X:

The constructible hierarchy,
is defined by transfinite recursion. In particular, at successor ordinals,
.
The difficulty with this construction is that each of the levels is not closed under the formation of unordered pairs; for a given
, the set
will not be an element of
, since it is not a subset of
.
However,
does have the desirable property of being closed under Σ0 separation.[1]
Jensen's modification of the L hierarchy retains this property and the slightly weaker condition that
, but is also closed under pairing. The key technique is to encode hereditarily definable sets over
by codes; then
will contain all sets whose codes are in
.
Like
,
is defined recursively. For each ordinal
, we define
to be a universal
predicate for
. We encode hereditarily definable sets as
, with
. Then set
and finally,
.
Properties
Each sublevel Jα, n is transitive and contains all ordinals less than or equal to ωα + n. The sequence of sublevels is strictly ⊆-increasing in n, since a Σm predicate is also Σn for any n > m. The levels Jα will thus be transitive and strictly ⊆-increasing as well, and are also closed under pairing,
-comprehension and transitive closure. Moreover, they have the property that

as desired. (Or a bit more generally,
.[2])
The levels and sublevels are themselves Σ1 uniformly definable (i.e. the definition of Jα, n in Jβ does not depend on β), and have a uniform Σ1 well-ordering. Also, the levels of the Jensen hierarchy satisfy a condensation lemma much like the levels of Gödel's original hierarchy.
For any
, considering any
relation on
, there is a Skolem function for that relation that is itself definable by a
formula.[3]
Rudimentary functions
A rudimentary function is a Vn→V function (i.e. a finitary function accepting sets as arguments) that can be obtained from the following operations:[2]
- F(x1, x2, ...) = xi is rudimentary (see projection function)
- F(x1, x2, ...) = {xi, xj} is rudimentary
- F(x1, x2, ...) = xi − xj is rudimentary
- Any composition of rudimentary functions is rudimentary
- ∪z∈yG(z, x1, x2, ...) is rudimentary, where G is a rudimentary function
For any set M let rud(M) be the smallest set containing M∪{M} closed under the rudimentary functions. Then the Jensen hierarchy satisfies Jα+1 = rud(Jα).[2]
Projecta
Jensen defines
, the
projectum of
, as the largest
such that
is amenable for all
, and the
projectum of
is defined similarly. One of the main results of fine structure theory is that
is also the largest
such that not every
subset of
is (in the terminology of α-recursion theory)
-finite.[2]
Lerman defines the
projectum of
to be the largest
such that not every
subset of
is
-finite, where a set is
if it is the image of a function
expressible as
where
is
-recursive. In a Jensen-style characterization,
projectum of
is the largest
such that there is an
epimorphism from
onto
. There exists an ordinal
whose
projectum is
, but whose
projectum is
for all natural
. [4]
References