The material conditional (also known as material implication) is a binary operation commonly used in logic. When the conditional symbol is interpreted as material implication, a formula is true unless is true and is false.
In logic and related fields, the material conditional is customarily notated with an infix operator .[1] The material conditional is also notated using the infixes and .[2] In the prefixed Polish notation, conditionals are notated as . In a conditional formula , the subformula is referred to as the antecedent and is termed the consequent of the conditional. Conditional statements may be nested such that the antecedent or the consequent may themselves be conditional statements, as in the formula .
History
In Arithmetices Principia: Nova Methodo Exposita (1889), Peano expressed the proposition "If , then " as Ɔ with the symbol Ɔ, which is the opposite of C.[3] He also expressed the proposition as Ɔ .[4][5][6]Hilbert expressed the proposition "If A, then B" as in 1918.[1]Russell followed Peano in his Principia Mathematica (1910–1913), in which he expressed the proposition "If A, then B" as . Following Russell, Gentzen expressed the proposition "If A, then B" as . Heyting expressed the proposition "If A, then B" as at first but later came to express it as with a right-pointing arrow. Bourbaki expressed the proposition "If A, then B" as in 1954.[7]
Semantics
Truth table
From a classicalsemantic perspective, material implication is the binarytruth functional operator which returns "true" unless its first argument is true and its second argument is false. This semantics can be shown graphically in the following truth table:
F
F
T
F
T
T
T
F
F
T
T
T
One can also consider the equivalence .
The conditionals where the antecedent is false, are called "vacuous truths".
Examples are ...
... with false: "If Marie Curie is a sister of Galileo Galilei, then Galileo Galilei is a brother of Marie Curie."
... with true: "If Marie Curie is a sister of Galileo Galilei, then Marie Curie has a sibling."
The semantic definition by truth tables does not permit the examination of structurally identical propositional forms in various logical systems, where different properties may be demonstrated. The language considered here is restricted to f-implicational formulas.
Minimal logic: By limiting the natural deduction rules of this logic to Implication Introduction (I) and Implication Elimination (E), one obtains minimal logic (as discussed by Johansson).[11] See below.
Intuitionistic logic: By adding the rule Falsum Elimination (E), one obtains intuitionistic logic. See below.
Classical logic: If Reductio ad Absurdum (RAA) is also permitted, the result is classical logic. See below.
Material implication does not closely match the usage of conditional sentences in natural language. For example, even though material conditionals with false antecedents are vacuously true, the natural language statement "If 8 is odd, then 3 is prime" is typically judged false. Similarly, any material conditional with a true consequent is itself true, but speakers typically reject sentences such as "If I have a penny in my pocket, then Paris is in France". These classic problems have been called the paradoxes of material implication.[12] In addition to the paradoxes, a variety of other arguments have been given against a material implication analysis. For instance, counterfactual conditionals would all be vacuously true on such an account, when in fact some are false.[13]
In the mid-20th century, a number of researchers including H. P. Grice and Frank Jackson proposed that pragmatic principles could explain the discrepancies between natural language conditionals and the material conditional. On their accounts, conditionals denote material implication but end up conveying additional information when they interact with conversational norms such as Grice's maxims.[12][14] Recent work in formal semantics and philosophy of language has generally eschewed material implication as an analysis for natural-language conditionals.[14] In particular, such work has often rejected the assumption that natural-language conditionals are truth functional in the sense that the truth value of "If P, then Q" is determined solely by the truth values of P and Q.[12] Thus semantic analyses of conditionals typically propose alternative interpretations built on foundations such as modal logic, relevance logic, probability theory, and causal models.[14][12][15]
Similar discrepancies have been observed by psychologists studying conditional reasoning, for instance, by the notorious Wason selection task study, where less than 10% of participants reasoned according to the material conditional. Some researchers have interpreted this result as a failure of the participants to conform to normative laws of reasoning, while others interpret the participants as reasoning normatively according to nonclassical laws.[16][17][18]
Van Heijenoort, Jean, ed. (1967). From Frege to Gödel: A Source Book in Mathematical Logic, 1879–1931. Harvard University Press. pp. 84–87. ISBN0-674-32449-8.
Hilbert, D. (1918). Prinzipien der Mathematik (Lecture Notes edited by Bernays, P.).
Mendelson, Elliott (2015). Introduction to Mathematical Logic (6th ed.). Boca Raton: CRC Press/Taylor & Francis Group (A Chapman & Hall Book). p. 2. ISBN978-1-4822-3778-8.
Starr, Will (2019). "Counterfactuals". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Stenning, K.; van Lambalgen, M. (2004). "A little logic goes a long way: basing experiment on semantic theory in the cognitive science of conditional reasoning". Cognitive Science. 28 (4): 481–530. CiteSeerX10.1.1.13.1854. doi:10.1016/j.cogsci.2004.02.002.